CRONOS






The End of Time
                       The Next Revolution in Physics
                       JULIAN BARBOUR

                       A revolutionary new theory that attacks one of the foundation
                       stones of science--the existence of time

                       Richard Feynman once quipped that "Time is what happens when
                       nothing else does." But Julian Barbour disagrees: if nothing
                       happened, if nothing changed, then time would stop. For time is
                       nothing but change. It is change that we perceive occurring all
                       around us, not time. Put simply, time does not exist.

                       In this highly provocative volume, Barbour presents the basic
                       evidence for a timeless universe, and shows why we still experience
                       the world as intensely temporal. It is a book that strikes at the heart
                       of modern physics. It casts doubt on Einstein's greatest contribution,
                       the spacetime continuum, but also points to the solution of one of the
                       great paradoxes of modern science, the chasm between classical
                       and quantum physics. Indeed, Barbour argues that the holy grail of
                       physicists--the unification of Einstein's general relativity with
                       quantum mechanics--may well spell the end of time.

                       Barbour writes with remarkable clarity as he ranges from the
                       ancient philosophers Heraclitus and Parmenides, through the giants
                       of science Galileo, Newton, and Einstein, to the work of the
                       contemporary physicists John Wheeler, Roger Penrose, and Steven
                       Hawking. Along the way he treats us to enticing glimpses of some
                       of the mysteries of the universe, and presents intriguing ideas about
                       multiple worlds, time travel, immortality, and, above all, the illusion of
                       motion.

                       The End of Time is a vibrantly written and revolutionary book. It
                       turns our understanding of reality inside-out.

                            "This book is gold.... Barbour leaves his mark on every topic
                            he considers, including the arrow of time and the origins of the
                            Big Bang...his book is a masterpiece."--The New York Times
                            Book Review

                            "The orderly flow of events may really be as much an illusion
                            as the flickering frames of a movie. And according to
                            independent physicist Barbour's new book, even the apparent
                            sequence of the flickers is illusory.."--Time
 

                       New and recent titles of related interest:
                       General Science
 

                       Julian Barbour is a theoretical physicist who has worked on
                       foundational issues in physics and astronomy for 35 years. His first
                       book, the widely praised The Discovery of Dynamics, has recently
                       been republished in paperback. In 2000 the Association of American
                       Publishers awarded The End of Time its prestigious award for
                       excellence in the Physics & Astronomy section. Julian Barbour, a
                       theoretical physicist, has worked on foundational issues in physics
                       for 35 years. He _ is the author of the widely praised Absolute or
                       Relative Motion?: Volume I, and is working on the second volume.
Book review by Anthony Campbell. Copyright © Anthony Campbell (2001).
 

There have been many books about the paradoxes of time, but this one is far and away more paradoxical than most, for its thesis is
that time doesn't exist at all. This idea is explored in great detail, mostly in relation to physics but the philosophical and even the
theological implications are touched on in an Epilogue. In fact, Barbour himself is something of a paradox, for he is a respected
theoretical physicist who has remained independent, supporting himself and his family by translation while working on his ideas
about time whenever he could. However he continued to keep in touch with mainstream physics and he acknowledges help from a
number of well-known scientists, including Lee Smolin among others.

The book, he tells us, is intended to interest that fabled beast, the "general reader", but he also expects his colleagues to look over
his shoulder. He mentions Roger Penrose and Richard Dawkins as other scientists who have written similar types of books, and
his own will certainly bear comparison with theirs . Like those authors, Barbour is an excellent writer, and his interests include
philosophy, art, and literature as well as science so that his view of his subject is multidimensional; no nonsense about "two
cultures" here.

In the first part of the book, Barbour sets forth a number of basic ideas which are then progressively elaborated in later parts. The
central mystery that he confronts in his first three chapters is best described in his own words.

     "The main aim is to introduce a definite way of thinking about instants of time without having to suppose that they
     belong to something that flows relentlessly forward. I regard instants of time as real things, identifying them with
     possible instantaneous arrangements of all the things in the universe. They are configurations of the universe. In
     themselves, these configurations are perfectly static and timeless. But how and why can something static and
     timeless be experienced as intensely dynamic and temporal?"

These instants of time Barbour calls "Nows" or "time capsules". Examples include long-term memory stored within the brain,
fossils and geological records, and the human body, which contains within itself more time capsules nested one within another
(cells, genes). The universe is composed of things like this, and it exists within what Barbour calls Platonia, which is an
unimaginably vast configurational space. To help us understand what this means, Barbour uses the analogy of Triangle Land: the
different ways that triangles can be arranged in a configurational space. Much poring over of diagrams is needed here and
elswhere in the book if his argument is to be grasped, and my attempt to do so wasn't helped initially when a Necker cube illusion
made me think that a diagram was meant to represent a solid cube whereas it's really supposed to be hollow. A note in the legend
might have made this clearer.

In fact, this book does demand close attention from the reader, in spite of the beautiful clarity of the text. The difficulties are of at
least two kinds. One comes from the complexity of the physics. The theory that Barbour advances has profound implications for
both quantum mechanics and general relativity, and these implications are examined in considerable depth. Part of Barbour's thesis
is that his approach will reconcile these two fundamental scientific theories, something that ultimately baffled Einstein and has still
not been achieved. Certain more technical or more peripheral sections are enclosed in boxes, so the reader can skip them if
necessary, and other material is placed in the notes at the end. Even so, Barbour pays his reader the compliment of thinking that he
or she is willing to come to terms with some pretty deep ideas.

The other. and even more profound, kind of difficulty arises from the nature of the theory itself. We feel as if we have our being in
time. If there is no time, what meaning can we attach to the notions of past or future, and - even more difficult to accommodate -
our peception of motion? Barbour suggests that what we see as motion, in a leaping cat or a diving kingfisher, is really a series of
still photographs, which are somehow brought together by the brain to produce an illusion of movement. Of possible relevance here
is the very interesting fact that in certain kinds of brain damage the ability to perceive objects in motion is lost. Barbour mentions
this, but not the equally interesting observation, recorded by Oliver Sacks, that some patients suffering from post-encephalitic
Parkinsonism found themselves frozen in time for years, until released from this state, though only temporarily, by the drug
levodopa.

Trying to picture oneself in a timeless state is probably something like a fish would feel if it tried to picture itself out of the water.
Our language, of course, has no vocabulary to describe this, and Barbour finds himself repeatedly forced to use temporal language
to describe his theory, even though he acknowledges that this is just shorthand. Indeed, even if he is right, will it ever be possible to
feel that he is? The analogy that comes to mind here is with the shift from a geocentric to a heliocentric universe that took place in
the sixteenth century; no doubt many people, and not only churchmen, found that hard to come to terms with, but the imaginative
shift from a time-based to a timeless universe would be incomparably bigger.

But is Barbour right? This is a mainly technical question for physicists and cosmologists, but he does suggest some ways in which
the theory can be tested; in other words, it is intended to be physics, not metaphysics. Neverthless, profound metaphysical
questions are inevitably raised. Does free will exist? Is there room for a Creator? Where is Heaven (and Hell)? Is time travel
possible? Doesn't the denial of motion and change take all the joy out of life? Some of these are old chestnuts, of course, but they
would need to be radically re-evaluated if Barbour's theory were to become widely accepted. And, of course, the field is open for
anyone who wants to have a go; Barbour merely opens the way for us to think about the implications. For himself, he finds that his
ideas, and those of Lee Smolin (who wrote "The Life of the Cosmos"), tend towards pantheism. "The whole universe ... is the
closest we can get to a God."
DISCOVER Vol. 21 No. 12 (December 2000)
  Table of Contents

  From Here to Eternity
  Imagine a universe with no past or future, where time
  is an illusion and everyone is immortal. Welcome to
  that world, says physicist Julian Barbour
  By Tim Folger

  Time seems to stand still in south newington, a secluded village ringed by rolling
  green hills about 20 miles north of Oxford, England. The 1,000-year-old
  baptismal font in the town's church, the thatch-roofed houses, and the tidy
  gardens along narrow lanes all appear unchanged by the passage of centuries.
  Standing on the roof of the church's bell tower on a warm, late-summer day,
  Julian Barbour, a theoretical physicist with some extraordinary notions about the
  nature of time, points to his home, known as College Farm, which borders the
  ancient church.

  "It looks almost exactly as it did when it was built 340 years ago," says Barbour.
  "The barn is also from the 17th century. Virtually all the houses you see around
  are from about 1640 to 1720. The long, low house is the one I grew up in.
  That's my parents' house. It dates from about 1710 to 1720." The entire scene is
  so placid one can't help but imagine that Barbour's childhood home, as well as
  the village and the surrounding landscape, will remain unchanged for the next
  340 years.

  Such utter quiescence suits Barbour, who is convinced the static harmony of
  South Newington extends past the horizon to the universe at large. In his view,
  this moment and all it holds— Barbour himself, his American visitor, Earth, and
  everything beyond to the most distant galaxies— will never change. There is no
  past and no future. Indeed, time and motion are nothing more than illusions.

  In Barbour's universe, every moment of every individual's life— birth, death,
  and everything in between— exists forever. "Each instant we live," Barbour
  says, "is, in essence, eternal." That means each and every one of us is immortal.
  Like the perpetually unmoving lovers in Keats's "Ode on a Grecian Urn," we
  are "for ever panting, and for ever young." We are also for ever aged and
  decrepit, on our deathbeds, in the dentist's chair, at Thanksgivings with our
  in-laws, and reading these words.

  Barbour fully realizes how outrageous the notion of a world without time
  sounds. "I still have trouble accepting it," he says. But then, common sense has
  never been a reliable guide to understanding the universe— physicists have
  been confounding our perceptions since Copernicus first suggested that the sun
  does not revolve around Earth. After all, we don't feel the slightest movement
  as the spinning Earth hurtles through the void at some 67,000 miles per hour.
  Our sense of the passage of time, Barbour argues, is just as wrongheaded as
  the credo of the Flat Earth Society.

  Barbour has been preoccupied with studying the basic properties of time for
  four decades. It's an issue he believes most theoretical physicists have
  ignored."Given what a fascinating thing time is, it's surprising how few
  physicists have made a serious attempt to study time and say exactly what it is,"
  he says. "It's an unusual gap." At the outset Barbour didn't think he would have
  any fresh insights he could bring to the topic. "I don't regard myself as being at
  all talented. I struggle to do equations," he says, laughing. "But I just got very
  interested in the subject and found that very few people have really thought
  seriously about it."

  Perhaps Barbour himself wouldn't have been able to devote nearly 40 years of
  his, well, time to the problem if it hadn't been for his unique background. Unlike
  most of his colleagues, he doesn't work at a university or a government lab— he
  is one of the world's few freelance theoretical physicists. Nevertheless, his
  credentials are solid, and prominent physicists take him— and his
  unconventional ideas— quite seriously.

  "He has some wild ideas, but he definitely knows what he's talking about when
  it comes to these fundamental issues," says Carlo Rovelli, who works at the
  Center for Theoretical Physics in Luminy, France. Lee Smolin, a theoretical
  physicist at Pennsylvania State University, agrees: "Barbour is one of the few
  people I know who went out on their own and succeeded in doing several things
  that were important and would not have been easy to do in a conventional
  career."

  After receiving his doctorate in physics from the University of Cologne in 1968,
  Barbour, who is now 63, decided he didn't want to follow a traditional academic
  career, with the inevitable pressure to publish or perish. So he supported his
  wife and four children by translating Russian scientific articles and worked on
  physics on the side, publishing scholarly papers every few years. Outside
  academia, he was free to explore his interest in time without worrying about
  tenure or funding for what might seem an arcane pursuit.

  Until recently, Barbour's provocative work was little known beyond a rarefied
  circle of physicists. That changed earlier this year with the publication of his
  latest book, The End of Time, in which he presents his case for a universe
  where time, despite all appearances to the contrary, plays no role.

  Barbour's central argument is that a mistaken belief in the reality of time
  prevents physicists from achieving their ultimate goal: the unification of the
  submicroscopic atomic world of quantum mechanics with the vast cosmic one
  of general relativity. The problem arises because each theory provides a
  radically different conception of time, and physicists simply don't know how to
  reconcile the two views. Until they do, they will never have one seamless
  theory of the universe comprising the very smallest objects to the very largest.
  And certain middling-sized objects— human beings— will never understand the
  true nature of time and existence.

  What makes the two versions of time so different? Time in the quantum realm
  has no remarkable properties at all. In theories of quantum mechanics, time is
  essentially taken for granted; it simply regularly ticks away in the background,
  just as it does in our own lives. Like a clock at a sporting event, it provides an
  invisible framework in which events unfold. That's not the case in Einstein's
  general theory of relativity.

  To describe the universe on the largest scale, Einstein had to weave time and
  space together into the very fabric of the universe. As a result, in general
  relativity, there is no invisible framework, no clock ticking outside the universe
  against which to measure events. How could there be? Time and space joined
  together have weird consequences: Space and time curve around stars and
  other massive bodies and make light bend away from straight-line paths. Near
  black holes, time seems to slow down or even come to a full stop.

  Barbour is not alone in recognizing that the pictures of time in general relativity
  and quantum mechanics are fundamentally incompatible. Theoretical physicists
  around the world, spurred by Nobel dreams, sweat over the problem. But
  Barbour has taken perhaps the most unorthodox approach by proposing that the
  way to solve the conundrum is to leave time out of the equations that describe
  the universe entirely. He has been obsessed with this solution for more than 10
  years, since he learned of a vexing mathematical tour de force by a young
  American physicist named Bryce DeWitt.

  DeWitt, with the help of the eminent American physicist John Wheeler,
  developed an equation in 1967 that apparently melded quantum mechanics with
  general relativity. He did this by taking the principles from quantum mechanics
  that describe the interactions of atoms and molecules and applying them to the
  entire universe, a mind-bending feat not unlike trying to make a jockey's suit fit
  Michael Jordan.

  Specifically, DeWitt hijacked the Schrödinger equation, named for the great
  Austrian physicist who created it. In its original form, the equation reveals how
  the arrangement of electrons determines the geometrical shapes of atoms and
  molecules. As modified by DeWitt, the equation describes different possible
  shapes for the entire universe and the position of everything in it. The key
  difference between Schrödinger's quantum and DeWitt's cosmic version of the
  equation— besides the scale of the things involved— is that atoms, over time,
  can interact with other atoms and change their energies. But the universe has
  nothing to interact with except itself and has only a fixed total energy. Because
  the energy of the universe doesn't change with time, the easiest of the many
  ways to solve what has become known as the Wheeler-DeWitt equation is to
  eliminate time.

  Most physicists balk at that solution, believing it couldn't possibly describe the
  real universe. But a number of respected theorists, Barbour and Stephen
  Hawking among them, take DeWitt's work seriously. Barbour sees it as the
  best path to a real theory of everything, even with its staggering implication that
  we live in a universe without time, motion, or change of any kind.

  Strolling in the meadows of oxford's Christ Church College with Julian Barbour,
  time and motion seem undeniable. Towering cumulus clouds float overhead,
  ferried by a gentle breeze. Children run and shout in the same field where Alice
  Liddell, the girl who inspired Lewis Carroll's Alice's Adventures in
  Wonderland, often played. How can there be no time, no movement? Barbour
  settles his tall, lean frame into the grass, readying himself for a long explanation
  to yet another skeptic. He begins with what seems a most straightforward
  proposition: Time is nothing but a measure of the changing positions of objects.
  A pendulum swings, the hands on a clock advance. Objects— and their
  positions— he argues, are therefore more fundamental than time. The universe
  at any given instant simply consists of many different objects in many different
  positions.

  That sounds reasonable, as it should, coming from a thoughtful gentleman like
  Barbour. But the next part of his argument— the crux of his view— is much
  harder to swallow: Every possible configuration of the universe, past, present,
  and future, exists separately and eternally. We don't live in a single universe that
  passes through time. Instead, we— or many slightly different versions of
  ourselves— simultaneously inhabit a multitude of static, everlasting tableaux that
  include everything in the universe at any given moment. Barbour calls each of
  these possible still-life configurations a "Now." Every Now is a complete,
  self-contained, timeless, unchanging universe. We mistakenly perceive the
  Nows as fleeting, when in fact each one persists forever. Because the word
  universe seems too small to encompass all possible Nows, Barbour coined a
  new word for it: Platonia. The name honors the ancient Greek philosopher who
  argued that reality is composed of eternal and changeless forms, even though
  the physical world we perceive through our senses appears to be in constant
  flux.

  Before allowing himself to be interrupted by the stream of questions he knows
  will come, Barbour continues to press his point. He likens his view of reality to a
  strip of movie film. Each frame captures one possible Now, which may include
  blades of grass, clouds in a blue sky, Julian Barbour, a baffled Discover writer,
  and distant galaxies. But nothing moves or changes in any one frame. And the
  frames— the past and future— don't disappear after they pass in front of the
  lens.

  "This corresponds to the way you remember highlights of your life," Barbour
  says. "You remember very vividly certain scenes as snapshots. I remember
  once, very tragically, I had to go to a man who had shot himself. And I still have
  no difficulty in recalling the scene of opening the door just to where he was at
  the foot of the stairs and seeing him there with the gun and the blood. It's still
  imprinted as a photograph on my mind. Many other memories I have take that
  form. People have strong visual memories. If it's not just a snapshot, it might be
  a few stills of a movie you recall. Think of perhaps your most vivid memories.
  You don't think of them as just lasting a second. You see them as snapshots in
  your mind's eye, don't you? They don't fade— they don't seem to have any
  duration. They're just there, like the pages of a book. You wouldn't ask how
  many seconds a page lasts. It doesn't last a millisecond, or a second; it just is."

  Barbour calmly awaits the inevitable sputtering objections.

  Don't we then somehow shift from one "frame" to another?

  No. There is no movement from one static arrangement of the universe to the
  next. Some configurations of the universe simply contain little patches of
  consciousness— people— with memories of what they call a past that are built
  into the Now. The illusion of motion occurs because many slightly different
  versions of us— none of which move at all— simultaneously inhabit universes
  with slightly different arrangements of matter. Each version of us sees a
  different frame— a unique, motionless, eternal Now. "My position is that we
  are never the same in any two instants," Barbour says. "Obviously, as
  macroscopic human beings, we don't change much from second to second. And
  there's no question that we're the same people. I mean only an extreme
  madman would deny that," he says reassuringly. "To that extent, it's true that
  we do move from one Now to another. But in what sense can you say we're
  moving? The way I see it, not exactly the same information content, but nearly
  the same information content, is present in many different Nows." Nothing
  really moves, he says.

  "The information content or the consciousness that makes us aware of being
  ourselves, of having a certain identity, is just present in many different Nows.
  There are two things that distinguish my position from what people might just
  intuitively think. First of all, the Nows are not on one timeline. They're just
  there. And second, there is nothing corresponding to motion. I'm taking a very
  radical position on that. I'm saying the Nows are really like snapshots. The
  impression of motion only arises because the snapshots have got an
  extraordinarily special structure." We are part of that special structure.

  For all the apparent complexity of his scheme, Barbour believes that it provides
  the simplest way to merge quantum mechanics and relativity into a single theory
  of the universe. Like all physicists, he strongly believes that mathematically
  elegant explanations tend to be true, even if they conflict with common sense. "I
  think the approach I'm proposing does deserve to be taken seriously," he says.
  "It would be extremely rash and stupid to say it's definitely right, but there's an
  inner logic to these ideas. They're very natural. If we want to put quantum
  mechanics and general relativity together, what is the simplest way that could
  be done? I believe it is the way I've proposed. And I believe it is essentially the
  way that Bryce DeWitt discovered in 1967 when he found his infamous
  equation."

  Barbour stands and brushes some grass from his pants. He has to meet his
  wife, Verena, for dinner and looks at his watch, grinning as he does so. "This is
  what comes of saying there is no time— I have to pull my own leg sometimes,"
  he says.

  Walking to a fashionable new restaurant on Oxford's old High Street, Barbour
  talks about how his ideas have changed his perceptions of the world. "I think it's
  completely wrong to say that the world was created in the Big Bang and that it
  was the unique creation event." Barbour hastens to add that there exists an
  eternal Now that contains the Big Bang, but he sees it as just one of an infinite
  array of Nows existing alongside this instant on High Street. "Immortality is all
  around us," he says. "Our task is to recognize it."

  How does the physics community react to such ideas? Physicists who know
  Barbour's work agree that it shouldn't be dismissed out of hand. At a physics
  conference in Spain, Barbour conducted an informal poll. He asked how many
  of the physicists believed that time would not be a part of a final, complete
  description of the universe. A majority were inclined to agree.

  Don Page, a cosmologist at the University of Alberta in Edmonton who
  frequently collaborates with Stephen Hawking, raised his hand that day. "I think
  Julian's work clears up a lot of misconceptions," says Page. "Physicists might
  not need time as much as we might have thought before. He is really
  questioning the basic nature of time, its nonexistence. You can't make technical
  advances if you're stuck in a conceptual muddle." Strangely enough, Page feels
  that Barbour might actually be too conservative. When physicists finally iron
  out a new theory of the universe, Page suspects that time won't be the only
  casualty. "I think space will go too," he says cryptically.

  Like Page, Carlo Rovelli applauds Barbour for forcing physicists to think about
  things they may have taken for granted. "It's time to go back to the big
  questions," he says. "We need a new way to think about the world. There are
  major philosophical challenges, and Julian is a part of that." Barbour, meanwhile,
  is still developing his theory. With Niall Ó Murchadha, an Irish physicist, he is
  attempting to formulate a modification of general relativity in which not only
  time but also distance plays no role. In particular, his theory would predict that
  the universe, being static, is not expanding. The main evidence that physicists
  have for the expansion— the pervasive stretching of the spectra of light from
  distant galaxies known as the cosmic redshift— would instead be explained by
  the gravitational effects of neutron stars and black holes.

  "If you want the wildly optimistic scenario," he says, "in which the Irishman and
  I develop this theory, make this prediction, and it turns out to agree with
  observations, then we would really be in the big time."

  The parish church next to Barbour's home contains some of the rarest murals in
  England. One painting, completed in about 1340, shows the murder of Thomas à
  Becket, the 12th-century archbishop whose beliefs clashed with those of King
  Henry II. The mural captures the instant when a knight's sword cleaves
  Becket's skull. Blood spurts from the gash. If Barbour's theory is correct, then
  the moment of Becket's martyrdom still exists as an eternal Now in some
  configuration of the universe, as do our own deaths. But in Barbour's cosmos,
  the hour of our death is not an end; it is but one of the numberless components
  of an inconceivably vast, frozen structure. All the experiences we've ever had
  and ever will have lie forever fixed, set like crystalline facets in some infinite,
  immortal jewel. Our friends, our parents, our children, are always there. In
  many ways it's a beautiful and comforting vision. But the question still nags:
  Could it possibly be true? Only time will tell.

                 Is There Life After Death?

  Julian Barbour is convinced we are all immortal. Unfortunately, in a timeless
  universe immortality does not come with the same kind of perks that it does on
  Mount Olympus. In Barbour's vision, we are not like Greek gods who remain
  forever young. We still have to buy life insurance, and we will certainly seem to
  age and die. And instead of life after death, there is life alongside death. "We're
  always locked within one Now," Barbour says. We do not pass through time.
  Instead, each new instant is an entirely different universe. In all of these
  universes, nothing ever moves or ages, since time is not present in any of them.
  One universe might contain you as a baby staring at your mother's face. In that
  universe you will never move from that one, still scene. In yet another universe,
  you'll be forever just one breath away from death. All of those universes, and
  infinitely many more, exist permanently, side by side, in a cosmos of
  unimaginable size and variety. So there is not one immortal you, but many: the
  toddler, the cool dude, the codger. The tragedy— or perhaps it's a blessing— is
  that no one version recognizes its own immortality. Would you really want to be
  14 for eternity, waiting for your civics class to end?

  As odd as this vision of a timeless world might seem, Barbour believes there is
  something stranger still to ponder: the very fact of our existence. "Creation and
  the fact that anything is— this for me is the complete mystery," he says. "The
  fact that we are here is totally mysterious."
  — T.F.

1st Law and Newtonian space and time.

  One of the most important consequences of the First Law is that it defines what we mean by an inertial frame of reference.

              An inertial reference frame is a reference frame where isolated bodies are seen to move
                                  in straight lines at constant velocity.
 

An observer at rest with respect to an inertial frame of reference is called an inertial observer. The laws of physics devised by
Newton take a particularly simple form when expressed in terms of quantities measured by an inertial observer (such as positions,
velocities, etc.). For example, an inertial observer will find that a body on which no forces act moves in a straight line at constant
speed or is at rest.

All motion occurs in space and is measured by time. In Newton's model both space and time are unaffected by the presence or
absence of objects. That is space and time are absolute, an arena where the play of Nature unfolds. In Newton's words,

Absolute space in its own nature, without relation to anything external, remains always similar and immovable.

...absolute and mathematical time, of itself, and from its own nature, flows equally without relation to anything external,
and by another name is called duration.

Space and time were taken to be featureless objects which served as a universal and preferred reference frame (see Fig. 4.9 for
an illustration). A consequence of this is that a given distance will be agreed upon by any two observers at rest with respect to
each other or in uniform relative motion, for, after all, they are just measuring the separation between two immovable points in
eternal space. In the same way a time interval will be agreed upon by any two observers for they are just marking two notches on
eternal time.
 
 
 

                  Figure 4.9: Illustration of Newton's concept of space. The grids represent space
                     which are unaffected by the presence and properties of the objects in it.
 
 
 

Newton's assumptions about space and time are the foundation of his theory of Nature and were accepted due to the enormous
successes of the predictions. Eventually, however, experimental results appeared which disagreed with the predictions derived
from Newton's theory. These problems were traced to the fact that these basic assumptions are not accurate descriptions of space
and time (though they do represent a very good approximation): space and time are not absolute (Chaps. 6, 7) . The
realization that Newton's theory required revisions came to a head at the beginning of the XXth century. In the two decades from
1905 to 1925 a completely new framework was constructed and has now replaced Newton's ideas. These theories comprise the
special and general theories of relativity and quantum mechanics.

Do we know that the current theories of space and time are the truth? The answer is no: we do know that the current theories
explain all the data (including the one explained by Newton and more), but we cannot determine whether they represent the
ultimate theories of Nature. In fact, we expect them not to be the last word as there are many unexplained questions; for example,
why should the proton be precisely 1836.153 times heavier than the electron? Why should space have 3 and not 25 dimensions?
etc.

But in the 17th century there was no inkling of these problems and very few scientist questioned Newton's hypothesis. In particular
Newton constructed his mechanics to comply with Galilean relativity: an observer in uniform motion with respect to another
cannot, without looking outside his laboratory, determine whether he is at rest or not. And even if he looks outside, he cannot
decide whether he is in motion or the other observer is. In fact for two inertial observers moving relative to each other the
question, ``which of us is moving?'' is un-answerable and meaningless. The only thing to be said is that they have a certain relative
velocity.

Traveling Through Time NOVA ONLINE
               by Clifford Pickover

               What is time? Is time travel possible? For centuries, these
               questions have intrigued mystics, philosophers, and
               scientists. Much of ancient Greek philosophy was
               concerned with understanding the concept of eternity, and
               the subject of time is central to all the world's religions and
               cultures. Can the flow of time be stopped? Certainly some
               mystics thought so. Angelus Silesius, a sixth-century
               philosopher and poet, thought the flow of time could be
               suspended by mental powers:

                    Time is of your own making;
                    its clock ticks in your head.
                    The moment you stop thought
                    time too stops dead.

               The line between science and mysticism sometimes grows thin. Today physicists would agree that
               time is one of the strangest properties of our universe. In fact, there is a story circulating among
               scientists of an immigrant to America who has lost his watch. He walks up to a man on a New York
               street and asks, "Please, Sir, what is time?" The scientist replies, "I'm sorry, you'll have to ask a
               philosopher. I'm just a physicist."

               Most cultures have a grammar with past and future tenses, and also demarcations like seconds and
               minutes, and yesterday and tomorrow. Yet we cannot say exactly what time is. Although the study of
               time became scientific during the time of Galileo and Newton, a comprehensive explanation was
               given only in this century by Einstein, who declared, in effect, time is simply what a clock reads. The
               clock can be the rotation of a planet, sand falling in an hourglass, a heartbeat, or vibrations of a
               cesium atom. A typical grandfather clock follows the simple Newtonian law that states that the
               velocity of a body not subject to external forces remains constant. This means that clock hands
               travel equal distances in equal times. While this kind of clock is useful for everyday life, modern
               science finds that time can be warped in various ways, like clay in the hands of a cosmic sculptor.

                                               Science-fiction authors have had various uses for time
                                               machines, including dinosaur hunting, tourism, visits to
                                               one's ancestors, and animal collecting. Ever since the time
                                               of H.G. Wells' famous novel The Time Machine (1895),
                                               people have grown increasingly intrigued by the idea of
                                               traveling through time. (I was lucky enough to have chats
                                               with H.G. Wells' grandson, who told me that his
                                               grandfather's book has never been out of print, which is rare
                                               for a book a century old.) In the book, the protagonist uses a
                                               "black and polished brass" time machine to gain mechanical
                                               control over time as well as return to the present to bring
                                               back his story and assess the consequences of the present
                                               on the future. Wells was a graduate of the Imperial College
               of Science and Technology, and scientific language permeates his discussions. Many believe Wells'
               book to be the first story about a time machine, but seven years before 22-year-old Wells wrote the
               first version of The Time Machine, Edward Page Mitchell, an editor of the New York Sun, published
               "The Clock That Went Backward."

               One of the earliest methods for fictional time travel didn't involve a machine; the main character in
               Washington Irving's "Rip van Winkle" (1819) simply fell asleep for decades. King Arthur's daughter
               Gweneth slept for 500 years under Merlin's spell. Ancient legends of time distortion are, in fact, quite
               common. One of the most poetic descriptions of time travel occurs in a popular medieval legend
               describing a monk entranced for a minute by the song of a magical bird. When the bird stops
               singing, the monk discovers that several hundred years have passed. Another example is the
               Moslem legend of Muhammad carried by a mare into heaven. After a long visit, the prophet returns to
               Earth just in time to catch a jar of water the horse had kicked over before starting its ascent.

               Time travel is possible

               Today, we know that time travel need not be confined to myths, science fiction, Hollywood movies, or
               even speculation by theoretical physicists. Time travel is possible. For example, an object traveling
               at high speeds ages more slowly than a stationary object. This means that if you were to travel into
               outer space and return, moving close to light speed, you could travel thousands of years into the
               Earth's future.

               Newton's most important contribution to science was his mathematical definition of how motion
               changes with time. He showed that the force causing apples to fall is the same force that drives
               planetary motions and produces tides. However, Newton was puzzled by the fact that gravity
               seemed to operate instantaneously at a distance. He admitted he could only describe it without
               understanding how it worked. Not until Einstein's general theory of relativity was gravity changed
               from a "force" to the movement of matter along the shortest space in a curved spacetime. The Sun
               bends spacetime, and spacetime tells planets how to move. For Newton, both space and time were
               absolute. Space was a fixed, infinite, unmoving metric against which absolute motions could be
               measured. Newton also believed the universe was pervaded by a single absolute time that could be
               symbolized by an imaginary clock off somewhere in space. Einstein changed all this with his
               relativity theories, and once wrote, "Newton, forgive me."

               Einstein's first major contribution to the study of time occurred when
               he revolutionized physics with his "special theory of relativity" by
               showing how time changes with motion. Today, scientists do not see
               problems of time or motion as "absolute" with a single correct answer.
               Because time is relative to the speed one is traveling at, there can
               never be a clock at the center of the universe to which everyone can
               set their watches. Your entire life is the blink of an eye to an alien
               traveling close to the speed of light. Today, Newtonian mechanics
               have become a special case within Einstein's theory of relativity.
               Einstein's relativity will eventually become a subset of a new science
               more comprehensive in its description of the fabric of our universe.
               (The word "relativity" derives from the fact that the appearance of the
               world depends on our state of motion; it is "relative.")

               We are a moment in astronomic time, a transient guest of the Earth.
               Our wet, wrinkled brains do not allow us to comprehend many
               mysteries of time and space. Our brains evolved to make us run from
               saber-toothed cats on the American savanna, to hunt deer, and to
               efficiently scavenge from the kills of large carnivores. Despite our
               mental limitations, we have come remarkably far. We have managed
               to pull back the cosmic curtains a crack to let in the light. Questions raised by physicists, from
               Newton to Kurt Gödel to Einstein to Stephen Hawking, are among the most profound we can ask.

               Is time real? Does it flow in one direction only? Does it have a beginning or an end? What is eternity?
               None of these questions can be answered to scientists' satisfaction. Yet the mere asking of these
               questions stretches our minds, and the continual search for answers provides useful insights along
               the way.
 
 

Exactly what is it that we are
measuring?

<P>In his book &quot;Companion to the Cosmos&quot; John Gribbin states that
everybody knows what time is, but nobody can explain what it is, and that
in physics, the important thing about time is that it provides a reference
system (a set of coordinates) in which events can be ordered. One event
comes before or after another in this system. He goes on to say that it
is important that, although this defines an<B> </B>arrow of time, there
is no suggestion anywhere in the laws of physics that time actually flows
from the past through the present and into the future. An interesting point
that Gribbin goes on to make is that all times have equal status and that
this shows up most forcefully in Einstein's Special Theory of Relativity
where time is regarded as a fourth dimension, on an equal footing with the
familiar three dimensions of space. He says that you can imagine all of
space and time represented as a four dimensional spacetime map, on which
all of history, the present and the future of the universe can be represented.</P>

<P>If Einstein's Special Theory of relativity is right, then according to
Gribbin this raises interesting questions about the nature of destiny and
freewill - is the future 'already there' in some sense, just waiting for
our consciousness to move over it? But Gribbin goes on to say that the uncertainty
inherent in <A HREF="Quantum%20mechanics">Quantum Mechanics</A><B> </B>suggests
that a better theory of space and time, merging relativity and quantum theory,
may restore the vagueness of the future to the description of spacetime.</P>

<P>So did that help at all? Do you now have a feeling for what time actually
is? Test your knowledge and answer me this. When does the present become
the past and the future become the present? If I mention the word 'future'
you think of some distant event, maybe next year, next week, tomorrow, an
hour from now. How about a minute from now? that is still obviously the
future, and a second from now? well yes, it is still in the 'future'. A
thousandth of a second, a millionth of a second? A what precise time interval
does the future merge into the present and for how long before it merges
into the past? Does time unfold in a smooth continuous flow or in small
discreet steps? With the absence of time is the concept of 'always' possible?
How long does the present last and precisely what does 'now' mean?</P>

<P>It would appear to be impossible to define 'now' as a precise moment
in time that could be used as a universal standard. It seems to be a personal
experience as perceived by the individual, our own unique frame of reference.
In this sense time would appear to be a unique event to every observer,
and this is indeed in agreement with relativity. Even the speed at which
time passes is individual to the observer depending on their speed and on
the strength of any gravitational field they may happen to be in. The future
to is also unique to the observer depending on when the individual enters
the future light cone of an event. (See Stephen Hawking's 'A Brief History
of Time) So time appears to us to be something that we all experience differently
and not as some sort of universal standard. In this sense then, time is
not something real, but only something that we experience, in the same way
that we can experience pain although pain itself only exists in our minds
and not in the 'real' world. In other words, time is dependent on our consciousness.
Would then, for example, the universe continue to expand and evolve if it
did not contain sentient beings that could observe it? (I think that this
question has the same merit as asking - if a tree fell down in the forest
and there was nobody there to hear it, would it make a noise?) The answer
would be it doesn't matter, it would be meaningless to ask! If there were
no sentient beings in the universe, the question could not be raised!</P>

<P>If we look at time from the opposite view point we can consider the implications
of time not existing. The only condition that I can imagine for time not
existing is in an infinite eternal nothing as described in the previous
page. In this context the concept of 'always' is a fundamental requirement
of the very existence of nothing. If the universe does indeed exist in nothing
it must always exist in nothing, without a past, present or future because
these terms could not exist. See <A HREF="Origin%20of%20the%20universe%20">Where
did the universe come from?</A> This would suggest that 'always' requires
the absence of time.</P>

<P>An interesting observation regarding time as being relative is that individually
we have no way of determining the rate at which time is passing. An astronaut
travelling at near light speed would not be able to detect that time had
slowed down, it would only be apparent on his return to base when he compares
his clock with the base clock and observes a difference. While traveling
at near light speed our astronaut has no means of detecting that time has
slowed down, everything would appear to be perfectly normal aboard his space
craft. (A look out of the window would reveal that something was amiss,
but our astronaut could not prove if it is him that is moving or the objects
passing by!) A recent television program demonstrated the relationship of
movement and time to good effect by setting two atomic clocks to show the
same time to within a very accurate degree. One of the clocks was sent by
'plane from London to Tokyo and back while the other remained in the studio.
The two clocks were compared on return and the clock that had remained in
the studio was shown to be running slightly ahead. What does this simple
experiment tell us? It tells us that the effect is real, time really does
run slower for a moving object, it isn't just in our heads, clocks are not
sentient!</P>

<P>So is the effect of time running at different speeds a 'real ' effect
irrespective of whether or not it is being measured? No. We do not know
what time is doing when we are not measuring it. We would be making foolish
assumptions if we assumed that time always behaved the same way regardless
of whether or not it was being observed. We do not know! It is the same
as the behaviour of electrons in Quantum Mechanics, we do not know what
they are doing when we are not observing them. We can only know what is
taken place while we are observing.</P>

<P>So is time 'real'?</P>
 

<P>I dislike the idea that the future may be 'already there' just waiting
for us to pass over it, for as John Gribbin states, where does that leave
destiny and freewill? See <A HREF="Free%20Will">Do we have free will? </A>If
on the other hand the future is not already there, then where does that
leave the special theory of relativity ? If time is 'real' in the same way
that the other three dimensions are real, this would indicate that it does
exists and is there waiting for our consciousness 'to move over it'. How
much flexibility that allows for the future I do not know, but can only
hope that the uncertainty in quantum theory allows us a free choice of actions.</P>

<P>I think that time is the biggest mystery of them all, and that it is
somehow tied into and dependent upon our consciousness.</P>

<P>Not much of an answer is it? But how do you explain something that is
so apparent to us and so completely necessary to our every experience in
life, yet has no form? It is as though it <B>exists</B> only in our minds
even though its <B>effects</B> are <B>perceived</B> to be everywhere throughout
the universe.</P>



Return to Pantheon Homepage

Return to Synergetic Qabala Homepage

Go to Iona Miller Collected Works

File Created: 3/17/02
Last Updated: 7/25/02